Open subproblems in aligning a Task-based AGI

https://arbital.com/p/taskagi_open_problems

by Eliezer Yudkowsky Mar 15 2016 updated Apr 14 2016

Open research problems, especially ones we can model today, in building an AGI that can "paint all cars pink" without turning its future light cone into pink-painted cars.


MIRI and related organizations have recently become more interested in trying to sponsor (technical) work on Task AGI subproblems. A task-based agent, aka Genie in Bostrom's lexicon, is an AGI that's meant to implement short-term goals identified to it by the users, rather than the AGI being a Bostromian "Sovereign" that engages in long-term strategic planning and self-directed, open-ended operations.

A Task AGI might be safer than a Sovereign because:

This page is about open problems in Task AGI safety that we think might be ready for further technical research.

Introduction: The safe Task AGI problem

A safe Task AGI or safe Genie is an agent that you can safely ask to paint all the cars on Earth pink.

Just paint all cars pink.

Not tile the whole future light cone with tiny pink-painted cars. Not paint everything pink so as to be sure of getting everything that might possibly be a car. Not paint cars white because white looks pink under the right color of pink light and white paint is cheaper. Not paint cars pink by building nanotechnology that goes on self-replicating after all the cars have been painted.

The Task AGI superproblem is to formulate a design and training program for a real-world AGI that we can trust to just paint the damn cars pink.

To go into this at some greater depth, to build a safe Task AGI:

• You need to be able to identify the goal itself, to the AGI, such that the AGI is then oriented on achieving that goal. If you put a picture of a pink-painted car in front of a webcam and say "do this", all the AI has is the sensory pixel-field from the webcam. Should it be trying to achieve more pink pixels in future webcam sensory data? Should it be trying to make the programmer show it more pictures? Should it be trying to make people take pictures of cars? Assuming you can in fact identify the goal that singles out the futures to achieve, is the rest of the AI hooked up in such a way as to optimize that concept?

• You need to somehow handle the just part of the just paint the cars pink. This includes not tiling the whole future light cone with tiny pink-painted cars. It includes not building another AI which paints the cars pink and then tiles the light cone with pink cars. It includes not painting everything in the world pink so as to be sure of getting everything that might count as a car. If you're trying to make the AI have "low impact" (intuitively, prefer plans that result in fewer changes to other quantities), then "low impact" must not include freezing everything within reach to minimize how much it changes, or making subtle changes to people's brains so that nobody notices their cars have been painted pink.

• The AI needs to not shoot people who are standing between the painter and the car, and not accidentally run them over, and not use poisonous paint even if the poisonous paint is cheaper.

• The AI should have an 'abort' button which gets it to safely stop doing what it's currently doing. This means that if the AI was in the middle of building nanomachines, the nanomachines need to also switch off when the abort button is pressed, rather than the AI itself just shutting off and leaving the nanomachines to do whatever. Assuming we have a safe measure of "low impact", we could define an "abortable" plan as one which can, at any time, be converted relatively quickly to one that has low impact.

• The AI should not want to self-improve or control further resources beyond what is necessary to paint the cars pink, and should query the user before trying to develop any new technology or assimilate any new resources it does need to paint cars pink.

This is only a preliminary list of some of the requirements and use-cases for a Task AGI, but it gives some of the flavor of the problem.

Further work on some facet of the open subproblems below might proceed by:

  1. Trying to explore examples of the subproblem and potential solutions within some contemporary machine learning paradigm.
  2. Building a toy model of some facet of the subproblem, and hopefully observing some non-obvious fact that was not predicted in advance by existing researchers skilled in the art.
  3. Doing mathematical analysis of an unbounded agent encountering or solving some facet of a subproblem, where the setup is sufficiently precise that claims about the consequences of the premise can be checked and criticized.

Conservatism

A conservative concept boundary is a boundary which is (a) relatively simple and (b) classifies as few things as possible as positive instances of the category.

If we see that 3, 5, 13, and 19 are positive instances of a category and 4, 14, and 28 are negative instances, then a simple boundary which separates these instances is "All odd numbers." A simple and conservative boundary is "All odd numbers between 3 and 19" or "All primes between 3 and 19". (A non-simple boundary is "Only 3, 5, 13, and 19 are members of the category.")

E.g., if we imagine presenting an AI with smiling faces as instances of a goal concept to be learned, then a conservative concept boundary might lead the future AI to pursue only smiles attached to human heads, rather than tiny molecular smileyfaces (not that this necessarily solves everything).

If we imagine presenting the AI with 20 positive instances of a burrito, then a conservative boundary might lead the AI to produce a 21st burrito very similar to those. Rather than, e.g., needing to explicitly present the AGI with a poisonous burrito that's labeled negative somewhere in the training data, in order to force the simplest boundary around the goal concept to be one that excludes poisonous burritos.

Conservative planning is a related problem in which the AI tries to create plans that are similar to previously whitelisted plans or to previous causal events that occur in the environment. A conservatively planning AI, shown burritos, would try to create burritos via cooking rather than via nanotechnology, if the nanotechnology part wasn't especially necessary to accomplish the goal.

Detecting and flagging non-conservative goal instances or non-conservative steps of a plan for user querying is a related approach.

(Main article.)

Safe impact measure

A low-impact agent is one that's intended to avoid large bad impacts at least in part by trying to avoid all large impacts as such.

Suppose we ask an agent to fill up a cauldron, and it fills the cauldron using a self-replicating robot that goes on to flood many other inhabited areas. We could try to get the agent not to do this by letting it know that flooding inhabited areas is bad. An alternative approach is trying to have an agent that avoids needlessly large impacts in general - there's a way to fill the cauldron that has a smaller impact, a smaller footprint, so hopefully the agent does that instead.

The hopeful notion is that while "bad impact" is a highly value-laden category with a lot of complexity and detail, the notion of "big impact" will prove to be simpler and to be more easily identifiable. Then by having the agent avoid all big impacts, or check all big impacts with the user, we can avoid bad big impacts in passing.

Possible gotchas and complications with this idea include, e.g., you wouldn't want the agent to freeze the universe into stasis to minimize impact, or try to edit people's brains to avoid them noticing the effects of its actions, or carry out offsetting actions that cancel out the good effects of whatever the users were trying to do.

Two refinements of the low-impact problem are a shutdown utility function and abortable plans.

(Main article.)

Identifying ambiguous inductions

An 'inductive ambiguity' is when there's more than one simple concept that fits the data, even if some of those concepts are much simpler than others, and you want to figure out which simple concept was intended.

Suppose you're given images that show camouflaged enemy tanks and empty forests, but it so happens that the tank-containing pictures were taken on sunny days and the forest pictures were taken on cloudy days. Given the training data, the key concept the user intended might be "camouflaged tanks", or "sunny days", or "pixel fields with brighter illumination levels".

The last concept is by far the simplest, but rather than just assume the simplest explanation is correct (has most of the probability mass), we want the algorithm (or AGI) to detect that there's more than one simple-ish boundary that might separate the data, and check with the user about which boundary was intended to be learned.

(Main article.)

Mild optimization

"Mild optimization" or "soft optimization" is when, if you ask the Task AGI to paint one car pink, it just paints one car pink and then stops, rather than tiling the galaxies with pink-painted cars, because it's not optimizing that hard.

This is related, but distinct from, notions like "low impact". E.g., a low impact AGI might try to paint one car pink while minimizing its other footprint or how many other things changed, but it would be trying as hard as possible to minimize that impact and drive it down as close to zero as possible, which might come with its own set of pathologies. What we want instead is for the AGI to try to paint one car pink while minimizing its footprint, and then, when that's being done pretty well, say "Okay done" and stop.

This is distinct from [eu_satisficer satisficing expected utility] because, e.g., rewriting yourself as an expected utility maximizer might also satisfice expected utility - there's no upper limit on how hard a satisficer approves of optimizing, so a satisficer is not reflectively stable.

The open problem with mild optimization is to describe mild optimization that (a) captures what we mean by "not trying so hard as to seek out every single loophole in a definition of low impact" and (b) is reflectively stable and doesn't approve e.g. the construction of environmental subagents that optimize harder.

Look where I'm pointing, not at my finger

Suppose we're trying to give a Task AGI the task, "Give me a strawberry". User1 wants to identify their intended category of strawberries by waving some strawberries and some non-strawberries in front of the AI's webcam, and User2 in the control room will press a button to indicate which of these objects are strawberries. Later, after the training phase, the AI itself will be responsible for selecting objects that might be potential strawberries, and User2 will go on pressing the button to give feedback on these.

strawberry diagram

The "look where I'm pointing, not at my finger" problem is getting the AI to focus on the strawberries rather than User2 - the concepts "strawberries" and "events that make User2 press the button" are very different goals even though they'll both well-classify the training cases; an AI might pursue the latter goal by psychologically analyzing User2 and figuring out how to get them to press the button using non-strawberry methods.

One way of pursuing this might be to try to zero in on particular nodes inside the huge causal lattice that ultimately produces the AI's sensory data, and try to force the goal concept to be about a simple or direct relation between the "potential strawberry" node (the objects waved in front of the webcam) and the observed button values, without this relation being allowed to go through the User2 node.

strawberry diagram

See also the related problem of "Identifying causal goal concepts from sensory data".

More open problems

This page is a work in progress. A longer list of Task AGI open subproblems:

(…more, this is a page in progress)


Comments

Paul Christiano

On the act-based model, the user would say something like "paint all the cars pink," and the AI would take this as evidence about what individual steps the user would approve of. Effectiveness at painting all cars pink is one consideration that the user would use. Most of the problems on your list are other considerations that would affect the user's judgment.

The difference between us seems to be something like: I feel it is best to address almost all of these problems by using learning, and so I am trying to reduce them to a traditional learning problem. For example, I would like a human to reject plans that have huge side effects, and for the agent to learn that big side effects should be avoided. You don't expect that it will be easy to learn to address these problems, and so think that we should solve them ourselves to make sure they really get solved. (I think you called my position optimism about "special case sense.")

I might endorse something like your approach at some stage---once we have set everything up as a learning problem, we can ask what parts of the learning problem are likely to be especially difficult+important, and focus our efforts on making sure that systems can solve those problems (which may involve solving them ourselves, or may just involve differential ML progress). But it seems weird to me to start this way.

Some considerations that seem relevant to me:

It's possible that the difference between us is that I think it is feasible to reduce almost all of these problems to traditional learning problems, where you disagree. But when we've actually talked about it, you seem to have consistently opted for positions like "in some sense this is 'just' a prediction problem, but I suspect that solving it will require us to understand X." And concretely, it seems to me like we have an extremely promising approach for reducing most of these problems to learning problems.

Paul Christiano

• You need to be able to identify the goal itself, to the AGI, such that the AGI is then oriented on achieving that goal\. This isn't trivial for numerous reasons\. If you put a picture of a pink\-painted car in front of a webcam and say "do this", all the AI has is the sensory pixel\-field from the webcam\. Should it be trying to achieve more pink pixels in future webcam sensory data? Should it be trying to make the programmer show it more pictures? Should it be trying to make people take pictures of cars? Assuming you can in fact identify the concept that singles out the futures to achieve, is the rest of the AI hooked up in such a way as to optimize that concept?

I was talking to Chelsea Finn about IRL a few weeks ago, and she said that they had encountered the situation where they

At which point it positioned the block so that it looked (to its cameras) like the block was in a slot, while in fact it was far away.

I think they then added joint position information so that the AI could more reliably estimate whether the block was in the slot, and that fixed the problem.

Of course this problem can be solved in many ways and this instance doesn't illustrate the full difficulty etc. but I think it's a nice illustration anyway.

Paul Christiano

The problem of conservatism is an extension of the supervised learning problem in which, given labeled examples, we try to generate further cases that are almost certainly positive examples of a concept, rather than demanding that we label all possible further examples correctly\. Another way of looking at it is that, given labeled training data, we don't just want to learn a simple concept that fits the labeled data, we want to learn a simple small concept that fits the data \- one that, subject to the constraint of labeling the training data correctly, predicts as few other positive examples as possible\.

Presumably the advantage of this approach---rather than simply learning to imitate the human burrito-making process or even human burritos, is that it might be easier to do. Is that right?

I think that's a valid goal, but I'm not sure how well "conservative generalizations" actually address the problem. Certainly it still leaves you at a significant disadvantage relative to a non-conservative agent, and it seems more natural to first consider direct approaches to making imitation effective (like bootstrapping + meeting halfway).

Of course all of these approaches still involve a lot of extra work, so maybe the difference is are expectations about how different research angles will work out.

Paul Christiano

In the context of a Task AGI, one application of what we call 'conservatism' is the Burrito Problem\. Suppose I show the AI five burritos and five non\-burritos\. Rather than learning the simplest concept that distinguishes burritos from non\-burritos and then creating something that is maximally a burrito under this concept, we would like the AI to learn a simple and narrow concept that classifies these five things as burritos according to some simple rule \(not just the rule, "only these exact five objects are burritos"\) but which also classifies as few other objects as burritos as possible\. This concept however must still be broad enough to permit the construction of a sixth burrito that is not molecularly identical to any of the first five\. But not so broad that the burrito includes butolinum toxin \(because, hey, anything made out of mostly carbon\-hydrogen\-oxygen\-nitrogen that looks like a burrito ought to be fine\)\.

To me, the most natural way to approach this is to take a probability distribution over "what it means to be a burrito," and to produce a thing that is maximally likely to be a burrito rather than a thing which is maximally burrito-like. Of course this still depends on having a good distribution over "what it means to be a burrito" (as does your approach).

Paul Christiano

To put it another way, the task is to have the AI generate a safe burrito\. One way to try to do this is making sure that the AI's explicit training data contains a burrito with butolinum toxin, labeled as a negative example, so that the AI knows not to include butolinum\. The hope is that via conservatism we can avoid needing to think of every possible way that our training data might not properly stabilize the 'simplest explanation' along every dimension of potentially fatal variance, and shift some of the workload to just showing the AI positive examples which happen not to contain butolinum toxin\.

It seems critical to distinguish the cases where

  1. We are hoping the AI generalizes the concept of "burrito" in the intended way to new data,
  2. The definition of burrito is "something our burrito-identifier would identify as a burrito given enough time," and we are just hoping the AI doesn't make mistakes. (The burrito-identifier is some process that we can actually run in order to determine whether something is a burrito.)

As you've probably gathered, I feel hopeless about case (1).

In case (2), any agent that can learn the concept "definitely a burrito" could use this concept to produce definitely-burritos and thereby achieve high reward in the RL game. So the mere existence of the easy-to-learn definitely-a-burrito concept seems to imply that our learner will behave well. We don't have to actually explicitly do any work about conservative concepts (except to better understand the behavior of our learner).

I've never managed to get quite clear on your picture. My impression is that:

I think your optimism about case (1) is defensible; I disagree, but not for super straightforward reasons. The main disagreement is probably about case (2).

I think that your concern about generating a good enough burrito-evaluator is also defensible; I am optimistic, but even on my view this would require resolving a number of big research problems.

I think your concern about mistakes, and especially about something like "conservative concepts" as a way to reduce the scope for mistakes, is less defensible. I don't feel like this is as complex an issue---the case for delegating this to the learning algorithm seems quite strong, and I don't feel you've really given a case on the other side.

Note that this is related to what you've been calling Identifying ambiguous inductions, and I do think that there are techniques in that space that could help avoid mistakes. (Though I would definitely frame that problem differently.) So it's possible we're not really disagreeing here either. But my best guess is that you are underestimating to the extent to which some of these issues could/should be delegated to the learner itself, supposing that we could resolve your other concerns (i.e. supposing that we could construct a good enough burrito-evaluator).

Emma Borhanian

If we see that 3, 5, 13, and 19 are positive instances of a category and 4, 14, and 28 are negative instances, then a simple boundary which separates these instances is "All odd numbers\." A simple and conservative boundary is "All odd numbers between 3 and 19" or "All primes between 3 and 19"\. \(A non\-simple boundary is "Only 3, 5, 13, and 19 are members of the category\."\)

Is this really more complex than "All primes between 3 and 19"? I think you need more numbers before you can import the definition of prime and have that be simple.

Ryan Carey

the strawberry diagrams are currently unavailable